IMAGINING
OTHER
POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY - A
PRIMER
Edmund Burke, Tom Paine,
and the French Revolution of 1789 (pp11)
Links: Imagining Other Index page
Political Philosophy Contents Page
Additional Sources:
Ball,
T. and Dagger, R. – Ideals and Ideologies, a Reader – Harper-Collins 1991. 0
321 00539 2: has extracts from Burke,
Paine, and the
Introduction:
These
two writers are taken together, since they quarrelled in their reaction to the
French Revolution. They also represent two opposing ideologies: conservatism
(Burke) and radical liberalism (Paine). Some would say that Burke is more a
true philosopher than Paine, but in my view this is not fair, and both are
important: Burke for warning of the dangers of trying to shape society
according to abstract concepts and ideals, and as a representative of traditional
English Conservatism; Paine for foreseeing the welfare state, as well as
American independence from Britain.
(i) Edmund Burke 1729 –
1797.
Life:
Burke
was born in
Beliefs:
1.
he supported the Americans because, firstly, he believed revolution to be justified in order to regain or “restore”
something lost: Americans were being taxed, and their payments were
benefiting the British exchequer, but they had no votes – they had therefore,
as Burke saw it, lost their rights as English citizens. The slogan “no taxation
without representation” was based on his arguments.
2.
He not only opposed the French
Revolution but was deeply shocked by it: here was the overthrow of a long-established government of a type that was
widespread. He agreed that the political elite (aristocrats) had not been
carrying out their responsibilities well, but thought it would be better to
return to an order which did work than to bring in a new, untried system. In 1790 he wrote Reflections on the Revolution in
3.
Burke’s other objections to the French revolutionaries were that ideas of “natural rights” were dangerous, as they
could be taken to extremes by
anyone; they were too “abstract” – to demand their fulfilment is very likely to
lead to violence. “By having a right to everything they want everything.” (See
the Extracts from Reflections, first paragraph, and 8 below on Burke’s ideas on
natural rights).
The
important question is not the “right to food” but how to ensure people get food
(See the Extracts from Reflections, second paragraph). The revolutionaries were using “reason” in an
arrogant way (perhaps the English are less “philosophical” than the French, and
more pragmatic?).
4.
The ideas of the “philosophes” and revolutionaries had no background, no
tradition; but collective experience
builds up tradition and we know what “works” because of this. These points
(and others) are very much a part of conservative thinking: whatever has been
developed and tried over a long period of time - custom, tradition - should not be rashly discarded. For Burke, the
English institutions of Monarchy and Parliament had evolved since at least the
11th century, and thus were legitimate.
5.
The art of establishing the constitution
of a state is complex and intricate, and requires “delicate complicated skill”
and deep knowledge of human nature, and how to provide for human needs,
etc. (See the Extracts, second paragraph). The state is not an association for
expediency (like a commercial organisation) but it is an “overarching entity”
that keeps historical continuity going. This is an organic model: all the parts in society are inter-dependent, and play
their natural roles.
6.
For Burke (in complete contrast to Paine!) it was “natural” to feel awe at monarchs, “reverence to priests” etc. The
reverse of this is a tendency, which Burke shared, to view ordinary citizens as fallible, or ignorant; each has only a little
reason and cannot envisage the whole of society. We can only draw on
experience, and “prejudice”, not on individual abstract “reason”. Burke’s
advocating “prejudice” may seem
strange to our modern ears, but what he argued was that the word meant to
“pre-judge” in the light of our previous experience. In contrast, “reason” need
not be based on experience at all (for example, Aquinas’s belief was that our
reason is derived from God’s will). (See
the Extracts, final column).
7.
Moreover, our “natural” condition is dependency and the need for security and
leadership. Our “natural rights”, he
argued, are derived from society – the natural rights the revolutionaries
demanded were not derived from tradition or existing culture, and it was
dangerous – and brutal - to try to impose them on society. He condemned their
views as “ideology”. As regards Rousseau, he pointed out that “freedom” and
“equality” are rights which we gave up when we joined civil society: surely the
revolutionaries are asking to go back to pre-civil society (an impossibility!)?
8.
Burke identified “concrete” rights, derived from society and experience, to:
-
justice (though he didn’t define this);
-
the fruits of one’s industry (and though we all have equal freedom that doesn’t
mean equal entitlement);
-
continuity and inheritance;
-
education and religion – and Burke believed that religion was the most useful
and powerful guide to how to run society.
He
also seems to have supported Hobbes’s argument that there was a “residual”
right to rebel, in order to ensure that government was doing its duty to
protect the citizens.
9.
As regards who should govern, Burke’s argument is consistent: only those who have experience and
background are able to govern – thus the “aristocracy” is literally the
“best”. Their role is also more important because they have more “invested” in
society.
10.
The people, on the other hand, should be “tractable and obedient” – if they do
not get rewards in this life, they will in Heaven. The most important goal for
society is good order (“the foundation of all things”), and government can
bring this provided it acts to restrain
“human passions”. (Extracts, first paragraph).
11.
Government is “a contrivance of human wisdom to provide for human wants” (See
the Extracts, first paragraph). Burke supported a balance of powers in government, as was the practice in
12.
Burke is not opposed to change, but
argues (like Sir Karl Popper in the 20th century) that it should be “piecemeal” – the more
sweeping a change is, the more difficult it is to control, and the more
likelihood of violence.
Burke’s influence on
modern political thought:
The
strand in modern conservatism that Burke leads onto is “one nation” Toryism
(and until Macmillan the Conservative Party was aristocratic). However, in his
view that revolutions have historical causes (and are not just a result of new
ideologies) he is in agreement with Marx (who acknowledged Burke’s point). The
“New Right” was a departure from Burke’s viewpoint, in its hostility to
tradition…
(Notes
primarily from lectures given by John Moore at
(ii) Tom Paine 1737 –
1809.
Life and Writings:
Tom
Paine had the most extraordinary life – as an active political figure in
Revolutionary America and Revolutionary France, and even spending time in
prison! So these notes will start with a fair amount of biography.
He
was born, however, in “ordinary circumstances” in Thetford,
After
trying a number of different trades (including as a customs officer, from which
post he was dismissed) he served as a Councillor in Lewes (
He
became a pamphleteer, and one of his early pamphlets made the case that the
excise-men’s pay should be improved: here he argued that the rich could not
understand the poor and so should not represent them.
From
a writer of pamphlets he became incredibly influential both in
Paine
went to
While
serving as a drummer in the American revolutionary army, Paine wrote a series
of pamphlets (one on his drum-skin!) such as The American Crisis; one of the
earliest attacks on slavery (1775) – in which he drew an analogy with the
position of the Americans: why did they complain of “slavery” to the British
when they held slaves themselves?
In
1776 he wrote Common Sense, which defended
His
writing is powerful: “we have it in our power to begin the world over again…
and every opportunity to form the noblest, purest constitution on the face of
the earth.”
He
was the first to predict the “
In
1777 he was made Secretary of the Congress Committee of Foreign Affairs. He went to
In
1791 his book the Rights of Man (Part I) was published,
with Part II following in 1792. Note that although the work was published after
Burke’s Reflections, it was written before Burke published – it is often
thought that Paine was replying to Burke but this is not the case!
Part
I deals with general principles of government, and argues in support of:
popular sovereignty, universal suffrage, natural rights, and the French
revolutionary slogan: “liberty, equality, fraternity”.
He
also makes the significant point that in politics one generation cannot bind
the next – which has implications for the “social contract” idea. (see point 7
below).
In
Part II he continues, with an attack on monarchy – describing it as “a silly
and contemptible thing”. He called the Bill of Rights a “bill of wrongs and
insults” and said that British politics could not be based on a constitution
since this was unwritten, and nobody could therefore refer to it. In Part II
there are also strikingly modern suggestions for progressive taxation which
would be used to pay for social services (from the cradle to the grave!).
In
In
He
immediately published The Age of Reason
(which he had started writing before his imprisonment): this was an attack on
religious superstitions and false systems of theology and government based on
them. Part III was very anti-clerical. He was accused of atheism – but it is
clear that this is not justified (his ideas are “deist”).
In
1797 he published Agrarian Justice, which advocates
inheritance tax, and argues that civilisation thus far has increased poverty
not decreased it.
In
1802 he went to
In
this adventurous life he therefore had an influence on the drawing up of both
the Déclaration des Droits de l’Homme, and the American Declaration of
Independence.
Ideas:
Although
Paine was not a systematic philosopher, it is possible to draw the following ideas from his writings:
1.
“Common sense”: this is a
fundamental attribute of human psychology. It is the ability to know whatever
is spontaneously knowable. He also described it as the way the mind understands
what the heart feels (combining feeling, moral intuition, and reason?). Common
sense cannot be repressed for long, because if this happens the result (as in
Common
sense also enables us to identify our natural rights (see below). When people
become the property of others (slaves) then common sense is impaired (but not destroyed),
and it can be impeded by prejudice (“the spider of the mind” spins cobwebs over
it).
Therefore:
“… reason (freed from impostures of tradition and absurdities of religion)
could easily apprehend the natural laws
of society and government.”
[Is
this just a rhetorical argument?
2.
Also, the science of government is “of all things the least mysterious
and the most easy to understand”.
What has happened is that it has been “enveloped... [with] mystery, for the
purpose of enslaving plundering and imposing upon mankind”.
“By
the simple operation of constructing government on the principles of society
and the rights of man, every difficulty retires.” (But see point 12 below…)
The
simplest form of government is the most easily “repaired when disordered.” (See
Extracts from Common Sense).
[This
is contrary to Burke, in a sense, as the latter saw government and society as
naturally complex… Also, ecology teaches us that complexity helps survival.
3.
Paine drew a distinction between society and government: “society is produced by our wants, and government by our wickedness.”
(See Extracts from Common Sense, opening paragraph). Society is therefore
natural, and – presumably so long as people can cease being wicked - government
should simply do those “few” things
which society cannot do for itself. (See also point 12 below). Government
is then, at best, a necessary evil.
4.
Everyone has a common interest in pursuing safely their own interest, and a natural love of liberty. We all have
“inextinguishable feelings to do good, and the right to reason for ourselves.”
Therefore we all have natural rights
to “act for our own comfort and happiness” which precede the establishment of
government, so government has no right to interfere in them.
5.
The rights of man comprise both natural rights and civil rights: the latter
are acquired as a result of being a member of society, where our individual power is not enough to ensure our own
rights. Rights are, “by reciprocity” duties:
“Whatever is my right as a man is also the right of another; and it becomes my
duty to guarantee as well as to possess.” Consequently, Paine advocated freedom of opinion, religion etc.
6.
“Sovereignty as a matter of right,
appertains to the nation only, and not to any individual.” This is because
the original social contract could only have been made among the people – the
government did not exist at the time and so could not be a party to it!
7.
A social contract can only bind the
generation that agreed to it. It cannot “govern beyond the grave”, to bind
one generation to what was agreed by a previous generation. (See the Extract
from The Rights of Man).
(See
also the last paragraph of the Extracts from Common Sense…)
So,
hereditary monarchy is not natural:
“all hereditary government is in its nature tyranny.” “Monarchy is popery of government; a thing
kept to amuse the ignorant, and quiet them into paying taxes.” Not only is
hereditary government wrong in principle, it is harmful in practice, as had
happened in
Whoever
reveres kings has “given up the proper dignity of a man, [and] sunk himself
beneath the rank of animals, and contemptibly crawls like a worm.”
To
be a king requires only the animal figure of a man, a sort of breathing
automaton… [kings are] monsters in the natural order.”
8.
“…a nation has at all times an inherent and indefeasible right to abolish any form of government it finds inconvenient, and
establish such as accords with its interests, disposition and happiness.”
Society needs all its “parts” to be operating – which actually happens in a
revolution! Revolutions are not exactly natural, but occur when a people’s
feelings have been kept under for a long time, and their anger eventually
raises their consciousness to do something about their condition.
9.
A “balance of powers” is only needed if there are divisions within the ruling
groups (monarchy, aristocracy etc).
10.
All have rights to self-government, therefore in small states, direct democracy could be practised,
and otherwise representative democracy
is the only legitimate form. Moreover,
property qualifications for voting are wrong.
11.
Once government has been set up on the correct principles (the rights of man),
there would be no war – “man is not the
enemy of man, but through the medium of a false system of government.”
12.
Without war there would be less poverty (as war is costly), and more money
would be available for such welfare provisions as: maternity allowances, marriage grants, funeral grants, family
allowances, unemployment relief and pensions. All these are actually
proposed by Paine in Part II of The Rights of Man, published in 1792…
[This
surely implies an active government – is this in contradiction to what Paine
said about the simplest governments being the easiest to repair (points 2 &
3)?