IMAGINING OTHER
How
Enlightened was the Enlightenment?
Links:
Imagining Other Index page
Week 2 Notes:
Values of the
Enlightenment.
Introduction:
Roy Porter
concludes his 2001 book on The Enlightenment with the statement:
‘We are still trying to solve the problems of
the modern, urban industrial society to which the Enlightenment was midwife.’
However, he
adds: ‘In our attempts to [solve these
problems] we largely draw upon the techniques of social analysis, the
humanistic values, and the scientific expertise which the philosophes generated. We remain today the Enlightenment’s
children.’
Enlightenment Values:
It is
important to understand the new ideas that were promoted - what I call ‘values’
- and to see how they were related to the values and outlook of previous ages,
and of the (contemporary…) ancien
rėgime:
With each
of these ‘values’ we will need to note (‘Discussion’):
(i) ‘qualifications’ i.e. the exact meaning
of each ‘value’ is not as simple as at first glance!
(ii) that
there were also, in some cases, quite strong differences of opinion on each –
marked ‘however’ below.
(iii) that
there have also been criticisms made
since the period, which are also noted.
1. humanism
As pointed out
above (week 1), Kant exemplifies the
humanist approach with his belief that we have an individual core which should
dare to know, argue and find out. Another way of seeing this, as O’Hara puts
it, is that Enlightenment thinkers turned to new sources of authority;
enlightenment was not to be found in the Bible (as it had been in previous
centuries), nor in tradition, but humans had the capacity to search out
knowledge and identify the truth by themselves.
Alexander Pope
(1688 – 1744) wrote a famous couplet that sums up this view (and note there is
no denial of God here...):
‘Know then thyself, presume not God to scan
The proper study of Mankind is
There is
also a connection between humanism and the new astronomical knowledge (the new
helio-centred vs. the old geo-centred model – see next week). Reason and
experience were the new paths to knowledge. This point is expanded below.
It is
important, I believe, not to claim that humanism originated in the enlightenment
– in the 16th and 17th centuries, the Renaissance and
Protestantism had begun to turn away from the established, church-dominated
outlook, where the flesh was seen as sinful, and where the spirit and spiritual
life took precedence over mere earthly matters. We could say that the
Enlightenment was the culmination of this move.
So:
-
Aristotle, the Bible etc. were replaced by scientific authority – 17th
and 18th cc.
- in regard
to political ideas, the theory of the Divine Right of Kings was replaced by the
social contract (in the 17th and 18th centuries),
- the
expectation that all citizens should have the same religion was replaced by
religious tolerance – in the 18th c.
A number of
the other values listed here follow, it seems to me, from this humanist
philosophy (especially the importance of reason, the belief in progress, and in
the freedom of the individual).
Discussion:
1. Humanism:
1.1 qualifications:
-
restrictions: as O’Hara (2010 p2) points out, this humanism was restricted to men, who had a superior
role to women – e.g. Kant said reason is not trusted by most men, and not
trusted by all women.
- Kant was
also elitist in regard to the ‘great
unthinking masses.’ Porter (2001) suggests that the movement was in reality the
emergence of a ‘secular intelligentsia’ – i.e. an elite.
1.2 however:
- we can
contrast these ‘elitist’ approaches with Rousseau’s
faith in the will of the people, expressed in his belief in the ‘general will.’ Though Rousseau was not
simply putting trust in the whole population: the general will must be for the
good of the people, and it is not necessarily the same as the ‘will of
all’. Still, Rousseau’s ideas were
sufficiently radical as to contribute to the build-up to the French Revolution
of 1789. This is an example of the variety of views held by Enlightenment
thinkers.
1.3 criticisms made since:
- the religious
criticism: the rejection of religion has produced
materialism, and hence greed and selfishness. This point, of course, applies
even more to the next value:
- although
we live in an age which is still largely humanist, and secular, the resurgence
of religious
fundamentalism marks a continuing opposition to humanism, I would
argue. In other words, humanism has not been universally accepted.
2. secularism
Secularism
- the disbelief in religion - is an aspect of humanism, but one that I think is
worth considering separately. It went with scepticism and the rejection of
authority, in Enlightenment thought.
Discussion:
2.1 qualification:
Porter
(2001 ch 4) points out that there is a danger of over-simplification: e.g.
Voltaire was not opposed to all religion. Although Voltaire is famous for
having said, of the church and its power,
that we should: écrasez l’infame
(crush the infamy), and this seems extreme, we must recognise that
Enlightenment thinkers lived in a time of lack of freedom of speech, and of
authoritarian rulers. In order to get round the censor, and to appeal to the
public, they used slogans and, especially in Voltaire’s case, irony (O’Hara). The danger with this, of
course, is that you may be held to be saying something different to what you
really mean!
So it is
probably best to describe the views of Voltaire and others as deism – and this was a significant move
away from the sectarianism of preceding centuries (with their many ‘wars of
religion’). Religious belief was itself
marked by ‘reason’ – i.e. God would not have created a confusing world –
there should therefore be more agreement on the basic points in religion (and
we shouldn’t quarrel over trivial differences). Leibniz, for example, argued
that God would not have made an imperfect world… the idea of providence was
widespread. Even the English poet Alexander Pope wrote: whatever is, is right
(O’Hara 2010 p 7).
2.2 however:
See also Voltaire
on Leibniz in Candide – where Dr Pangloss is mocked for believing that ‘we live
in the best of all possible worlds’. The
2.3 criticisms made since:
(As
above, on humanism). Current discussion led by such as Dawkins
indicates that the religious world-view still has a lot of influence…
3. reason, based on experience and experiment
Clarification of the role of reason in
philosophy:
The
Enlightenment was based on the belief that everyone had the ability to reason,
and to discover truths from evidence. This belief, central to the
Enlightenment, is a mixture, as it were, of rationalism and empiricism.
‘Rationalism’ is the belief that
reasoning alone leads to understanding about the real world. The view that
perception is what leads us to understanding is ‘empiricism’.
John Locke (1632 – 1704), a founding figure in the
Enlightenment, argued that we learn by observing things (empiricism), and our perceptions tell us what is real. But at
the same time he believed in innate ‘human rights’ – which is not really
compatible with empiricism. With Voltaire, the folly of ignoring the real world
(extreme rationalism) is shown in his novel Candide, where Pangloss’s outlook
is ridiculed. Pangloss’s optimism was, says Porter (2001), based on the
Leibnizian metaphysical conviction that God has created the best possible
world.
Some implications of the emphasis on reason:
Since
Reason was universal, and God is the supreme deployer of reason, then humans
must be able to follow at least some of God’s thought. This idea, together with
the questioning of the idea of ‘original sin,’ – which had its roots in
Protestantism (the individual’s ability to reach out to God directly), led to
the view of human perfectibility (or
at least constant improvement!). Hence also ‘progress’...
(But note
that the Protestant emphasis on individual conscience
was a more radical idea than the individual’s ability to reason.) Catholicism
felt itself under threat from the emphasis on reason (O’Hara 2010).
Psychological theories were developed to show how
intrinsic is this ability to reason, and some (e.g. Locke) regarded it as a
type of perception, analogous to eyesight.
Truth was a central value – and ‘truth can hardly be
too modest’ (d’Alembert) i.e. one should speak out about it. (O’Hara 2010) See
below, however, under ‘criticisms’.
3.1 reason - qualification:
In the
Enlightenment, experience is central
(from
Enlightenment
thinkers were critics, not ‘rationalists’ (nor ‘irrationalists’) – after all,
they called themselves philosophes or
‘philosophers.’ The English word is, however, not equivalent to the French
word: philosophes were involved in
the world [engagé?] – journalists,
propagandists, activists… they believed in what, later, Marx would call praxis.
The philosophe was someone who dares to
think for himself, ‘trampling on prejudice, tradition, universal consent,
authority, in a word, all that enslaves most minds’… (Diderot and d’Alembert
defining philosophes in the
Encyclopédie – quoted in Porter 2001 p 3).
However,
just as one did not appeal to authority first any more, there was also less
interest in ‘mystery’, magic/alchemy
etc (O’Hara 2010). Marina Warner (in a book on the ‘Arabian Nights’ called
Stranger Magic (Chatto & Windus 2011)) makes the case that before the
Enlightenment ‘science, philosophy and art recognised no frontiers, that is in
both the Christian and the Islamic world) even though Christendom and Islam
were politically in conflict. Yet
this openness to different ideas closed somewhat from the Enlightenment on, and
east and west became more separate. In the Enlightenment, magic was ‘sealed
off’ from science, imagination from reason, and also east from west.’ At this
point, the Arabian Nights (a collection of Arab-Islamic texts, translated into
French early in the 18th century) became popular, as a form of
‘foreign magic’ which it was easy (easier than home-grown magic) to ‘disown, or
otherwise hold in intellectual or political quarantine.’ (These arguments draw
on the work of Edward Said on ‘orientalism’.)
See Robin
Yassin-Kassab’s review Observer 12.11.11. http://www.guardian.co.uk/books/2011/nov/11/stranger-magic-marina-warner-review?INTCMP=SRCH
3.2 reason - however:
There was
disagreement on the relative role and importance of reason in relation to the ‘passions’ (emotions). Pope argued that
reason balanced the passions, and Hume argued
that ‘reason is, and ought only to be,
the slave of the passions’. Rousseau saw the two interacting: ‘… the human understanding is greatly
indebted to the passions which, it is universally allowed, are also much
indebted to the understanding. It is by the activity of the passions that our
reason is improved, for we desire knowledge only because we wish to enjoy…’ (O’Hara 2010 p 12 – 13)
For Hume
and science see: science.
For
Rousseau and politics see:
3.3 reason - criticisms made at the time and
since:
Edmund Burke (1729 – 1797) and other conservatives believed
that it was dangerous to rely on ‘abstract reason’, especially when dealing
with the real world and the world of politics: here, experience and therefore
tradition should not be ruled out of court. (See Scruton’s account in his
Dictionary of Philosophy). If the values of tradition and community are
destroyed, and too much emphasis put on individual freedom, revolution, and
abstract ‘rights’ the result will be chaos and violence (as in the French
Revolution – and other similar events).
Recently,
David Brooks in his book: The Social Animal (2011) puts forward ideas about
‘how success happens’ (in society and politics), which are ‘steeped in the
anti-rationalist reflections of the British Enlightenment’ (Guardian article by
Stuart Jeffries, G2
Issues concerning ‘reason’ in the 20th
century and today:
1. Postmodern commentators also have a view that
is suspicious of ‘reason’ – for them, ‘reason’ was merely a term for the way
that a particular sector of a particular
society saw the world – it has no universal value. See also Political Philosophy Part 2: postmodernism. Foucault made a similar point by
demonstrating how beggars, petty criminals and the mentally sick were excluded
or institutionalised in the 18th century. (Further in Porter
Chapters 3,4).
2. Marxism. Porter (2001) points out that
the critical Marxist theorists Adorno and Horkheimer saw a link between
reason/science and absolutism - if science and reason encourage the view that
there is an absolute distinction between right and wrong, rather than there
being a plurality of ‘truths’ (‘discourses’ or ‘narratives’). (This seems odd to me, for surely Hume
pointed out that the kind of ‘reason’ we use in science is not the same as in
social science?)
3. New Age. On the other hand, we could
argue that ‘new age’ culture has brought back an interest in the mystical, spiritual,
etc. This viewpoint could be seen a similar to the romantic objection to the
Enlightenment: everything has been subjected to a ‘mechanical’, scientific
point of view, which has taken the mystery and beauty out of society.
4. A number
of books have been written reflecting on the nature of human reason. For example Daniel Khaneman: Thinking, Fast
and Slow, which adopts a psychological point of view.
The latter
idea has been used by Michelle Baddeley, in Copycats and Contrarians – this
looks at two different kinds of ‘herding instinct’ (the tendency to follow
others): [from a review by Kathryn Hughes, Guardian 28th July 2018]
the first depends on cognitive function
- i.e. the part of the brain that deals with slow, steady thinking, and
the second rests on emotion (the amygdala is active here). She claims there is
a region of the brain called the anterior cingulated cortex which mediates
between the two. All this also relates to the question that philosophers in the
enlightenment grappled with: do people mainly make decisions in their own
individual interest, or do they consider (the good of) the crowd? Can we use
‘group instinct’ in a way that works best for individuals and the crowd?
5.
‘Post-fact’ (‘fake news’ etc). With the election of Donald Trump (2016), and
the spread of extreme right wing (alt-right) views, there is an increasing
tendency for the public to fall in with feelings rather than reason.
See also: Enlightenment - Conclusion.
4. individual
liberty
– the
eighteenth century saw the emergence of ideas of individual rights and
freedoms, also (O’Hara 2010) individual self-interest - especially in Locke
(1632 – 1704), Adam Smith (1723 – 1790) et
al…
(See my
other notes ..\pp9locke.htm ..\pp13
liberalism - adam smith.htm).
This
individualism probably arose with the changing class structure, and especially
the growth of a merchant class, and
its demands for freedom to travel and to trade being central.
Adam Smith formulated the idea that the free market
allows individuals to pursue their self-interest to the benefit of all. (Though
my view is that he did not approve of this, even though he suggested no
alternative to the market, and no remedy for its failings).
The (later)
philosophical theory that most clearly justified individualism (individuals
free to pursue their self-interest) was utilitarianism
– the pursuit of happiness was (self-evidently!) the only rational goal.
See ..\pp14
utilitarianism.htm
(O’Hara p2,
Outram p2) Kant did not think every individual should be free to reason (and
criticise the ruler) – he favoured an enlightened despot such as Frederick the
Great of Prussia – a high degree of freedom, as in a republic, would not in
fact produce the best thoughts (my words) ‘a lower degree of civil freedom
provides the mind with room for each man to extend himself to his full
capacity.’ He also argued that in our ‘official’ capacities (our calling, e.g.
the doctor, minister etc – what he [confusingly!] called the private sphere) we
should not be free in what we say –
but in what he called the public sphere (and what we would call private!) we
should be free: ‘The public [I think
we would say private] use of man’s reason must always be free, for it alone can
bring about Enlightenment.’
See also: Kant's ethics.
4.1 qualifications:
There were differences
in regard to the precise ‘nature’ of the individual: perhaps benevolence was
natural? Or (Rousseau) ‘natural’ man was more like the uncivilized ‘savage’ who
did not suffer from civilisation’s obsession with private property and status
etc. There was also discussion of the relative role of reason and the passions
noted above - 2.3 (b).
Anthony
Pagden (The Enlightenment and why it still matters, OUP 2013) places great
emphasis on ‘sympathy’ as a key Enlightenment value – along with ‘cosmopolitanism’...
Note, also,
that ‘nature’ is a key concept in the Enlightenment… but is it more than a
‘buzz word’? (A word used to ‘win’ arguments, but that when subjected to
scrutiny is ambiguous, or means different things to different people).
4.2 however:
See above
on Kant – he was not alone in being close to ‘enlightened despots’ (Diderot and
Catherine the Great for example)
4.3 criticisms made since:
There is a
strong criticism to be made of the ‘possessive
individualism’ of ‘liberal’ theory in the 17th and 18th
centuries (C.B. MacPherson): this freedom was only, in fact, for propertied
males; a point noted by feminists
as well, of course. Yet the theory claimed to be ‘universal’ – to be applied to
all humans (this claim to universality only makes sense, it could be argued, if
Locke and others simply didn’t see non-propertied men, or women, as fully
human).
Matthew
Taylor (chief executive of the RSA) in The Observer 09.09.12, argues that we
have moved away from ‘Enlightenment’ views: ‘individualism is the dominant
force of our times. But unlike classical or Enlightenment conceptions of the
good life well lived, it is a narrow and materialistic form of individualism.’
See: http://www.guardian.co.uk/commentisfree/2012/sep/09/matthew-taylor-big-problems-big-solutions?
The socialist
objection is similar: we are not atomised individuals, in competition
with each other, but we need to co-operate and share property and the proceeds
of labour. There is an alternative explanation of the origins and nature of the
Enlightenment here, as well: the real driving force was the accumulation of
wealth by the ruling classes, and it only benefited them, at the expense of
workers, and people in developing countries.
5. tolerance
Given the
combination of a search for new ways of thinking, based on experience or
experiment, together with scepticism of authority and faith in the individual,
it is obvious that tolerance must follow. This is especially true in contrast
with previous times, when intolerance of religious difference led to
persecution and civil war.
It was
(O’Hara 2010) a ‘very social movement’
– with much conversation, discussion, etc, in coffee-houses (London), clubs
such as the Lunar Society – bringing together industrialists and intellectuals,
in Birmingham, or the Select Society (Edinburgh), and in salons run by well-connected Parisian ladies (Mme d’Epinay, Sophie
de Condorcet et al). There were also new journals; The Spectator, The Rambler.
Note:
Anthony Pagden (2013) says that the goal of the Enlightenment was
‘cosmopolitanism’.
5.1 qualifications:
O’Hara (2010)
also points out that the ‘enlightened’ thinkers were particularly intolerant of
‘unenlightened’ people! (This goes with the point made below about elitism). He
quotes (p14) Leonard Krieger: they ‘were
in the anomalous position of writing on behalf of the whole society and at the
same time castigating large sections of it for chronic abuses – governments for
their inequities, aristocracies for their gratuitous privileges, and the masses
for their servility.’
5.2 however:
The
Enlightenment surely marked a great improvement on the intolerance of previous
times...
5.3 criticisms made since:
Our
present-day discussion over tolerance usually revolves around the question: how
far can it be allowed to go? Some believe we should not tolerate racist, and
not allow them a platform for their views. Others that dialogue is the only way
to deal with extremism.
‘Political
correctness’ (whether we like it or not!) is a recognition that there are
limits to how abusive and insulting we should be to each other.
6. belief in
progress – and confidence in human powers.
A belief in
progress follows from
‘Nature and nature’s laws lay hid in night,
God said ‘let
(Alexander
Pope)
Likewise
Locke’s position with regard to political laws facilitated the idea of
progress: he saw government as a mechanism which may need adjusting or even
replacing with a better-working model. The influence of the 1688 ‘Glorious
Revolution’ is important here: a ‘reasonable’ constitutional settlement was
arrived at, after the 17th century civil war and the execution of
the king.
We can say
that the Enlightenment was an optimistic age: there was also less nostalgia for
ancient
‘[A]ll
knowledge will be subdivided and extended; and knowledge, as Lord Bacon
observes, being power, the human powers will, in fact, be increased; nature,
including both its materials, and its laws, will be more at our command; men
will make their situation in the world abundantly more easy and comfortable;
they will probably prolong their existence in it, and will grow daily more
happy… Thus, whatever was the beginning of this world, the end will be glorious
and paradisiacal, beyond what our imaginations can now conceive.’ (O’Hara 2010 p 7 – 8).
6.1 qualifications:
Note Edmond
Burke’s differences with Tom Paine – the conservative view that we should
respect tradition etc, against the liberal view that radical change is needed
to improve things.
6.2 however:
Note
O’Hara’s points (above) about scepticism,
including that Bayle was sceptical of
6.3 criticisms:
Is it fair
to say that opinion on ‘progress’ is divided? Some nowadays would say we
continue to make progress – others employ the ecological objection: that
the whole notion has led us to damage and nearly destroy our environment (see
next week).